Product Code Database
Example Keywords: the legend -dungeon $53
barcode-scavenger
   » » Wiki: Rational Point
Tag Wiki 'Rational Point'.
Tag

In and algebraic geometry, a rational point of an algebraic variety is a point whose coordinates belong to a given field. If the field is not mentioned, the field of is generally understood. If the field is the field of , a rational point is more commonly called a .

Understanding rational points is a central goal of number theory and Diophantine geometry. For example, Fermat's Last Theorem may be restated as: for , the of equation x^n+y^n=1 has no other rational points than , , and, if is even, and .


Definition
Given a field , and an algebraically closed extension of , an over is the set of common zeros in of a collection of polynomials with coefficients in :
\begin{align}
& f_1(x_1,\ldots,x_n)=0, \\ & \qquad \quad \vdots \\ & f_r(x_1,\dots,x_n)=0. \end{align} These common zeros are called the points of .

A - rational point (or - point) of is a point of that belongs to , that is, a sequence (a_1,\dots,a_n) of elements of such that f_j(a_1,\dots,a_n) = 0 for all . The set of -rational points of is often denoted .

Sometimes, when the field is understood, or when is the field of , one says "rational point" instead of "-rational point".

For example, the rational points of the of equation

x^2+y^2=1
are the pairs of rational numbers
\left(\frac ac, \frac bc\right),
where is a Pythagorean triple.

The concept also makes sense in more general settings. A projective variety in over a field can be defined by a collection of homogeneous polynomial equations in variables x_0,\dots,x_n. A -point of written a_0,\dots,a_n, is given by a sequence of elements of , not all zero, with the understanding that multiplying all of a_0,\dots,a_n by the same nonzero element of gives the same point in projective space. Then a -point of means a -point of at which the given polynomials vanish.

More generally, let be a scheme over a field . This means that a morphism of schemes is given. Then a -point of means a section of this morphism, that is, a morphism such that the composition is the identity on . This agrees with the previous definitions when is an affine or projective variety (viewed as a scheme over ).

When is a variety over an algebraically closed field , much of the structure of is determined by its set of -rational points. For a general field , however, gives only partial information about . In particular, for a variety over a field and any of , also determines the set of - rational points of , meaning the set of solutions of the equations defining with values in .

Example: Let be the curve x^2+y^2=-1 in the affine plane over the Then the set of real points is empty, because the square of any real number is nonnegative. On the other hand, in the terminology of algebraic geometry, the algebraic variety over is not empty, because the set of points is not empty.

More generally, for a scheme over a and any commutative -algebra , the set of -points of means the set of morphisms over . The scheme is determined up to isomorphism by the ; this is the philosophy of identifying a scheme with its functor of points. Another formulation is that the scheme over determines a scheme over by base change, and the -points of (over ) can be identified with the -points of (over ).

The theory of Diophantine equations traditionally meant the study of integral points, meaning solutions of polynomial equations in the rather than the rationals For homogeneous polynomial equations such as x^3+y^3=z^3, the two problems are essentially equivalent, since every rational point can be scaled to become an integral point.


Rational points on curves
Much of number theory can be viewed as the study of rational points of algebraic varieties, a convenient setting being projective varieties. For smooth projective , the behavior of rational points depends strongly on the genus of the curve.


Genus 0
Every smooth projective curve of genus zero over a field is isomorphic to a conic (degree 2) curve in If has a -rational point, then it is isomorphic to over , and so its -rational points are completely understood.Hindry & Silverman (2000), Theorem A.4.3.1. If is the field of rational numbers (or more generally a ), there is an to determine whether a given conic has a rational point, based on the : a conic over has a rational point if and only if it has a point over all completions of that is, over and all


Genus 1
It is harder to determine whether a curve of genus 1 has a rational point. The Hasse principle fails in this case: for example, by Ernst Selmer, the cubic curve 3x^3+4y^3+5z^3 = 0 in has a point over all completions of but no rational point.Silverman (2009), Remark X.4.11. The failure of the Hasse principle for curves of genus 1 is measured by the Tate–Shafarevich group.

If is a curve of genus 1 with a -rational point , then is called an over . In this case, has the structure of a commutative (with as the zero element), and so the set of -rational points is an . The Mordell–Weil theorem says that for an elliptic curve (or, more generally, an ) over a number field , the abelian group is finitely generated. Computer algebra programs can determine the Mordell–Weil group in many examples, but it is not known whether there is an algorithm that always succeeds in computing this group. That would follow from the conjecture that the Tate–Shafarevich group is finite, or from the related Birch–Swinnerton-Dyer conjecture.Silverman (2009), Conjecture X.4.13.


Genus at least 2
Faltings's theorem (formerly the Mordell conjecture) says that for any curve of genus at least 2 over a number field , the set is finite.Hindry & Silverman (2000), Theorem E.0.1.

Some of the great achievements of number theory amount to determining the rational points on particular curves. For example, Fermat's Last Theorem (proved by Richard Taylor and ) is equivalent to the statement that for an integer at least 3, the only rational points of the curve x^n+y^n=z^n in over are the obvious ones: and ; and for even; and for odd. The curve (like any smooth curve of degree in ) has genus \tfrac{(n-1)(n-2)}{2}.

It is not known whether there is an algorithm to find all the rational points on an arbitrary curve of genus at least 2 over a number field. There is an algorithm that works in some cases. Its termination in general would follow from the conjectures that the Tate–Shafarevich group of an abelian variety over a number field is finite and that the Brauer–Manin obstruction is the only obstruction to the Hasse principle, in the case of curves.Skorobogatov (2001), section 6,3.


Higher dimensions

Varieties with few rational points
In higher dimensions, one unifying goal is the conjecture that, for any variety of over a number field , the set of -rational points of is not in . (That is, the -rational points are contained in a finite union of lower-dimensional subvarieties of .) In dimension 1, this is exactly Faltings's theorem, since a curve is of general type if and only if it has genus at least 2. Lang also made finer conjectures relating finiteness of rational points to Kobayashi hyperbolicity.Hindry & Silverman (2000), section F.5.2.

For example, the Bombieri–Lang conjecture predicts that a smooth of degree in projective space over a number field does not have Zariski dense rational points if . Not much is known about that case. The strongest known result on the Bombieri–Lang conjecture is Faltings's theorem on subvarieties of abelian varieties (generalizing the case of curves). Namely, if is a subvariety of an abelian variety over a number field , then all -rational points of are contained in a finite union of translates of abelian subvarieties contained in .Hindry & Silverman (2000), Theorem F.1.1.1. (So if contains no translated abelian subvarieties of positive dimension, then is finite.)


Varieties with many rational points
In the opposite direction, a variety over a number field is said to have potentially dense rational points if there is a finite extension field of such that the -rational points of are Zariski dense in . Frédéric Campana conjectured that a variety is potentially dense if and only if it has no rational fibration over a positive-dimensional of general type.Campana (2004), Conjecture 9.20. A known case is that every in over a number field has potentially dense rational points, because (more strongly) it becomes over some finite extension of (unless it is the over a plane cubic curve). Campana's conjecture would also imply that a K3 surface (such as a smooth quartic surface in ) over a number field has potentially dense rational points. That is known only in special cases, for example if has an elliptic fibration.Hassett (2003), Theorem 6.4.

One may ask when a variety has a rational point without extending the base field. In the case of a hypersurface of degree in over a number field, there are good results when is much smaller than , often based on the Hardy–Littlewood circle method. For example, the Hasse–Minkowski theorem says that the Hasse principle holds for quadric hypersurfaces over a number field (the case ). Christopher Hooley proved the Hasse principle for smooth cubic hypersurfaces in over when .Hooley (1988), Theorem. In higher dimensions, even more is true: every smooth cubic in over has a rational point when , by Roger Heath-Brown.Heath-Brown (1983), Theorem. More generally, Birch's theorem says that for any odd positive integer , there is an integer such that for all , every hypersurface of degree in over has a rational point.

For hypersurfaces of smaller dimension (in terms of their degree), things can be more complicated. For example, the Hasse principle fails for the smooth cubic surface 5x^3 + 9y^3 + 10z^3 + 12w^3 = 0 in over by Ian Cassels and Richard Guy.Colliot-Thélène, Kanevsky & Sansuc (1987), section 7. Jean-Louis Colliot-Thélène has conjectured that the Brauer–Manin obstruction is the only obstruction to the Hasse principle for cubic surfaces. More generally, that should hold for every rationally connected variety over a number field.Colliot-Thélène (2015), section 6.1.

In some cases, it is known that has "many" rational points whenever it has one. For example, extending work of and , János Kollár showed: for a cubic hypersurface of dimension at least 2 over a with not a cone, is unirational over if it has a -rational point.Kollár (2002), Theorem 1.1. (In particular, for infinite, unirationality implies that the set of -rational points is Zariski dense in .) The is a more precise statement that would describe the asymptotics of the number of rational points of bounded on a .


Counting points over finite fields
A variety over a has only finitely many -rational points. The Weil conjectures, proved by André Weil in dimension 1 and by in any dimension, give strong estimates for the number of -points in terms of the Betti numbers of . For example, if is a smooth projective curve of genus over a field of order (a prime power), then
\big| |X(k)|-(q+1)\big| \leq 2g\sqrt{q}.
For a smooth hypersurface of degree in over a field of order , Deligne's theorem gives the bound:Katz (1980), section II.
\big| |X(k)|-(q^{n-1}+\cdots+q+1)\big| \leq \bigg( \frac{(d-1)^{n+1}+(-1)^{n+1}(d-1)}{d}\bigg) q^{(n-1)/2}.

There are also significant results about when a projective variety over a finite field has at least one -rational point. For example, the Chevalley–Warning theorem implies that any hypersurface of degree in over a finite field has a -rational point if . For smooth , this also follows from Hélène Esnault's theorem that every smooth projective rationally chain connected variety, for example every Fano variety, over a finite field has a -rational point.Esnault (2003), Corollary 1.3.


See also
  • Arithmetic dynamics
  • Birational geometry
  • Functor represented by a scheme


Notes

External links
Page 1 of 1
1
Page 1 of 1
1

Account

Social:
Pages:  ..   .. 
Items:  .. 

Navigation

General: Atom Feed Atom Feed  .. 
Help:  ..   .. 
Category:  ..   .. 
Media:  ..   .. 
Posts:  ..   ..   .. 

Statistics

Page:  .. 
Summary:  .. 
1 Tags
10/10 Page Rank
5 Page Refs
1s Time